Saturday, October 26, 2013

Necropolitics at a Distance

Last week, Aaron raised an interesting question about the link between necropolitics and killing that takes place at a distance (temporal, spatial), proposing that “perhaps it’s possible to consider the necropolitical in relation to killing that occurs in belated or temporally discontinuous contexts.” The suggestion that “killing at a distance” may still be usefully included under the rubric of the necropolitical enables me to draw a connection between Mbembe’s work and The Picture of Dorian Gray and to see necropolitics at work in in the deaths of two lower-class characters: Sybil Vane, the actress who commits suicide when Dorian breaks off his engagement to her, and James Vane, her brother, who dies in an accidental shooting at Dorian’s hunting lodge.

In what way are these deaths, which the text uneasily names as murders -- “‘So I have murdered Sybil Vane,’ said Dorian Gray, half to himself, ‘—murdered her as surely as if I had cut her little throat with a knife’” (96) – properly necropolitical? They illustrate, in a way that admittedly strains the terms of Mbembe’s argument, a “power” that “refers and appeals to exception, emergency, and a fictionalized notion of the enemy” in order to establish and maintain a right to kill (Mbembe 16). Dorian and Lord Henry justify rhetorically, post-facto, the deaths of Sybil and James by framing both lower-class characters as potential dangers to Dorian’s existence: “If you had married [Sybil] you would have been wretched,” Henry suggests (97), and after seeing James’s corpse, Dorian weeps with relief, “for he knew he was safe” from any attempts by James to avenge his sister’s death (199). While the need to kill Sybil and James was not present while they were alive, Dorian is able to conjure it afterwards to assuage the guilt he feels for his role, however accidental, in their deaths.

This rhetorical slight-of-hand is helped by a preexisting right to kill that the upper class holds over the lower class, in practice if not in law, illustrated chillingly by Alan Campbell’s reaction to Dorian’s confession of the murder of Basil Hallward: “Murder!...I shall not inform upon you. It is not my business” (161). That is, while the lower class is not always framed as a dangerous enemy that needs to be killed in order for the upper class to survive, it is still constructed as a population that is eminently disposable. (This may go some way to explain Lord Henry’s ghoulish reduction of Sybil and James’s deaths to their aesthetic value, as “a wonderful scene [from a play]” (100) or “an annoying subject” (196), respectively.)

Also, to reconnect these murders-at-a-distance to Aaron’s example (the radioactive fallout to which “low-use segments” of the population were subjected as a result of nuclear testing), we can see that in both cases, while the deaths of specific subjects are unintended, the killing act was itself an assertion of the state/upper class’s right to kill. Testing nuclear bombs is itself an assertion of the right to use them in acts of war; on a smaller scale, the firing of guns at animals -- and the lower-class employees (beaters) whose job it is to drive them into the path of the upper-class hunters – is an act that asserts the right to kill, and it takes place in a setting (the hunting lodge’s extensive grounds) that symbolizes Dorian’s economic and political power. In both cases, a demonstration of power results in actual deaths.

What may bar these deaths from being usefully included in a consideration of necropolitics is not the distance between the act of killing and physical death, but in the missing intention to kill; here, murder is not the “primary and absolute objective” of the characters’ actions. Nevertheless, the characters’ assertion of the right to kill is the condition of possibility for the deaths, however casually unrelated the two events may appear, and the deaths therefore result from a kind of necropolitics.

Does extending an understanding of necropolitics to include the accidental or not-directly-intended deaths of disposable populations in addition to the deliberate murders of threatening ones – to include letting die as well as killing – assist or obscure our attempts to follow the operations of necropolitics in the world? Does the unpredictability of killing-at-a-distance point to a fatal flaw in necropolitical sovereignty? Or does it make such sovereignty appear all the more capacious and inescapable? 

2 comments:

Unknown said...

First--I really love your development of this notion of killing-at-a-distance (and not just because it's something I'm interested in as well). But is there any real distinction between what you call a "demonstration" of the power to kill and an "intentional" killing? I think Mbembe's arguments about sovereignty rely on the ways that these two categories slip into each other in the modern necropolitical state. But--having said that--the distinction you draw between killing and letting die is immensely useful, I think. Both of these are symptomatic of a general disregard for life. This disregard, the absence of the need to justify the act of killing, is perhaps characteristic of Mbembe's notion of sovereignty--which relies, as you state, on an appeal to states of exception and emergency. Maybe we are running up against the limits of Mbembe's necropolitics here by considering intentionality? Is this a route for producing an alternative notion of the necropolitical?

Ashley said...

Megan,
I found in your post three engaging threads pertaining to death: "the right to kill", "the intention to kill" and "letting die." These questions, as well as your case studies, do stretch the limits of necropolitics; in terms of Mbemebe's argument, neither the right nor the expressed intentionality of killing is important, only the exercising of the choice "to kill or to let live" matters. Your post, in these respects, asks on the more local level how these decisions to exercise this sort of sovereignty come about. What makes one feel justified "to kill"[the right of the upper class?], what provides the momentum to perform these killing tasks [intention, or lack of intention; direct murder, or something that could resemble murder]? Yet, if I recall properly, in Society Must Be Defined when Foucualt defines biopolitics--which Mbembe insists on inverting to Necropolitics --he states that it is the ability of the sovereign to "make live or let die." I wonder then, if your last thread, about the possibility to include "letting die" actually folds into the realm of Necropolitics as Mbembe would like, or actually goes 180 degrees into what Foucault insisted was the goal of biopolitics? And more pertinent, I would say, to the purposes of this blog post, how would an individual's ability to exercise killing as a right, intention or, letting, not just demonstrate sovereignty but actually create it? Does Dorian, by "letting" his erstwhile fiancee die or by accidentally shooting her brother dead, actually create power for himself beyond these isolated and incidental occurrences? Given that he finds his justification for these acts in temporally discontinuous contexts from the actual "acts" themselves, it seems there is evidence not just for "killing at a distance" but also "sovereignty-creation" at a distance.